In a previous article, I argued briefly that, despite
the common aesthetic problems of Novus Ordo
worship-style, it was not in the best interest of
traditionalists to focus on these deficiencies, but to
instead focus on the problematic nature of the new
prayers. Let me briefly say a bit more about this here.
I know a Catholic fellow who, while perfectly nice and
polite, I can’t seem to understand. He is pleasant
enough, to be sure. In fact, he is extremely generous
and kind.
But he doesn’t drink alcohol and he doesn’t follow
baseball. And for these reasons, I have a hard time
relating to him.
Actually, he doesn’t follow any sports. Of course, as
Catholics, we should be mostly concerned about his lack
of interest in God’s favored sport. I fear—for I’m
afraid to ask—that he doesn’t even really know the rules
of the game, let alone know any of the players, current
or past. I live in a city that has severe emotional
attachments to their baseball organizations; but as
baseball is God’s favorite game, this is one feature of
New York that I find virtuous, even heroically so. That
this colleague of mine does not participate in this
city-wide neurosis, I find disturbing.
As to the other of my colleague’s peculiar features, I
have it on good authority that he is neither recovering
from prior addictions nor reacting to other traumas: he
is simply averse to spirits of all sorts, and always has
been. As for me, while details are between me and my
confessor, I have no qualms in mentioning that I
appreciate a good pint in a pub. Wherever the Catholic
sun doth shine, indeed. How one would not like
this activity, I do not know.
So this acquaintance of mine: he baffles me. Now, not
drinking alcohol for no other reason than personal
preference, or worse yet, not loving baseball—these
are signs of social disorders in and of themselves, to
be sure. And where you find some disorders, you are
bound to find others. For our purposes, I should mention
one more peculiar quirk of this man. What I write next
should not surprise any of the readers of this fine
newspaper, given what I’ve written so far: this man, he
also cares rather little for the old mass or traditional
rubrics, and he rolls his eyes at those who agonize over
these adiaphora. This colleague of mine is perfectly
fine with versus populum and communion on (in?)
the hand, he cared not at all that—for example--the
recent beach party mass in Rio featured bikinied
‘ministers’ handing out hosts from plastic cups, and he
does not cry in horror at Paul VI Audience Hall or worse
yet, the wretched Domus Sanctae Marthae Chapel.
Moreover, as far I can tell, he seems content with the
hellishly awful music that infects his Paul VI Mass. The
music—dear God, the music—it seems to affect him
negatively not at all. Yes, he is a strange fellow.
Sneak Peek:
This article will be
featured in the next print edition
of The Remnant newspaper. Unlike this one, most
Remnant articles never appear on our website.
Click
here
to find out how you can become a subscriber
and never miss a single one of these excellent Remnant
articles.
I am not expert enough in the Ways of Man to say if his
frightening vision of the world is a product of barbaric
habituation, some sort of devilish, self-induced
beta-blocking, or a glitch in his DNA; but I’m quite
convinced that there is a connection between his
tee-totaling, his complete ignorance of and disinterest
in God’s favored game, and his ambivalence towards
liturgy. I haven’t done any sort of formal study, but
I’d be willing to bet that a large survey of the
American Catholic populace would reveal strong
connections between a disinterest in baseball and a
disinterest in good liturgy and good lager. This isn’t
to say that the best place to find those who appreciate
the Old Mass is the local pub on game night, but—no,
maybe that is the best place to find such people.
I don’t know: we should do a study (or just check the
pub and see, and while we’re there…).
This is all to say that we can speak not just of
conflicting visions of the good, but large divisions
over the nature of the beautiful. And these divisions
run deep. This makes sense, if one takes a rather
old-fashioned view of taste as something that
tracks, if ordered rightly, objectively beautiful
things. Those who have the virtue of good taste, argued
Aristotle, find (really) beautiful things beautiful.
Such a philosophy seems, prima facie, terribly
pretentious and elitist from our modern, egalitarian
perspective (and that Aristotle would include this
virtue in his ethical treatise, no less, makes us
gasp!). But once we get over our indignation, most are
resigned to admit that Aristotle is on to something
here. Indeed, even the utilitarians are happy to say,
along with John Stuart Mill, that there are higher
pleasures to be pursued, simply because we are humans
and not animals (I’ll leave it to the utilitarians to
figure out how Mill’s concession concerning the
insufficiency of the ‘satisfied pig’ doesn’t collapse
utilitarianism entirely). No, it seems perfectly correct
to speak of good taste and bad taste. And therefore it
seems perfectly correct—as terrible as this might
sound—to speak of the more refined tastes of those who
prefer certain liturgical rubrics over others.
But here is where our problem begins. Because forget
about bad liturgy for a second. Forget about communion
in the hand, songs about gathering, liturgical dancing,
and the barren wasteland of ‘ordinary time’. How, pray
tell, do you get someone who does not like baseball to
like it? I suppose you could answer: the same way that
you get someone to enjoy a good glass of wine. You get
them to acquire a taste for it.
Yes, acquisition and acclimation through habituation.
That’s the name of the game, to be sure. Aristotle is
right: proper habituation is everything. Assuming that
poor taste is not a result of faulty physiology, I
suppose we could get my colleague to like baseball by
dragging him to Yankee Stadium, in the same way that we
drag those at the bottom of Plato’s cave, kicking and
screaming, to the light.
But just as Plato’s cave dwellers have been habituated
to appreciate the shadows in their flickery darkness,
and just as they fastly flee back to the safety of the
darkness upon being dragged out by those in the know, my
baseball and beer-hating colleague will most certainly
be rather annoyed at my insistence that he must
accompany me once again to the afternoon game.
But drag him I must, one might argue.
And yes, the required tie-in to the Old Mass, can now be
briefly made, and some point about how the Old Mass
‘takes some getting used to’, and how this also requires
some acclimation by those not previously disposed to
such worship style, can be written. Of course. So
consider this here the requisite mentioning of this
point.
Very good. But enough about that. It is more important
to point out what a lousy state of affairs this is. For
the answer to our problems—habituation—has revealed a
troubling aspect of getting things right in the beauty
game. However successful this acclimating program for
our aesthetically-blind acquaintances might be, we
should note more importantly how, from the beginning, we
have recognized that there is simply no straightforward
appeal to reason available.
One cannot simply offer a written argument for the
beauty and grandeur of baseball, or Guinness, let alone
the Traditional Latin Mass. Believe me, I’ve tried with
my colleague regarding all three. It appears that it’s
habituation or nothing. If you do not see the
beauty of any of these things, the best I can do, given
my fortunate access to this ‘inside information’, is to
get you too to ‘try them’. I cannot present a PowerPoint
presentation for their aesthetic superiority (I’ve also
tried this), and expect anyone who isn’t already
convinced, to be convinced.
So enough about baseball and beer. If you do not see
the beauty of the Old Mass, of ad orientem, of the
Latin language, of Gregorian chant—if you do not
recognize the superiority of these forms of worship,
then nothing that anyone says about these
things will do any good. If someone has been poorly
habituated, then, as Aristotle rightly said, they will
see the ugly as beautiful, and the bad as good. Sadly, a
distorted sense of taste cannot be corrected by the
offering of a syllogism.
This isn’t to say that beauty isn’t rational. It’s
entirely rational, and therefore knowable. Beauty
supervenes on being, and being is intelligible. But not
all knowledge is built on a priori, self-evident
truths that can be found regardless of one’s lot in
life, simply by transcending the confines of a wrongly
encultured mind, and thinking upon things ‘purely’. To
think this is possible—this is one of the many myths of
the Enlightenment. Most certainly, there are deft
philosophical arguments for why certain things are
objectively beautiful and others are not (and many of
these arguments are right). Moreover, as the work of
Benedict XVI on liturgy attests, there are arguments
that connect good theology with good liturgy and proper
reverence and form. But Benedict does not proceed like
Euclid, by building up a large set of necessary truths
from initially posited self-evident principles. A
traditionalist cannot build up a logically air-tight
case for the insanity of communion in the hand.
Likewise, I cannot make an argument for the stupidity of
my colleague’s favorite hymn (you don’t want to know) in
such a way that reveals that he is in fact offering a
logical contradiction by disagreeing with me.
At the end of the day, after all arguments are made, and
all theological and philosophical matters unpacked and
explained, we still have to appeal to a proper vision of
reality in order to make our arguments for the
beautiful, and getting this proper vision takes some
real work on the part of the poorly trained. If one’s
eyes aren’t trained, then reading or arguing will only
do so much good.
So what does this mean? It means, among other things,
that if failure of a purely logical appeal to the
beautiful is impossible, then we should not be surprised
that so many in the world of the Novus Ordo simply can’t
see what traditionalists see, and we should not be
surprised, moreover, that Novus Ordo types get annoyed
at traditionalists constantly pointing out to them their
ridiculous music, their architectural disasters, and
their irreverent forms of worship. Traditionalists
cannot proceed by axioms, but neither can they hold up a
CD of Tomás
Luis de Victoria in one hand, pound their other hand on
the table, and declare, “If you’d just LISTEN to
this, you’d understand!” It’s not that easy.
This isn’t to say that we should cease trying to train
those who are amenable to being trained. And drag we
must our friends to the Old Mass. But in the meantime,
we can appeal to aspects of the Old Mass that require no
habituation or privileged vision to understand. There
are features of the Old Mass that are superior to the
New Mass, but that require no inside information to
grasp.
The prayers. The content of the Old Mass. If there is
any straightforward ‘empirical’ or strictly ‘scientific’
argument to be made, if there is any argument that does
not transgress the so-called fact/value divide, if there
is any appeal to the superiority of the Old Mass that
does not threaten the sensibilities of those who
actually like songs about gathering, it’s the
prayers themselves.
We do not need to properly habituate or reorient
anyone’s vision to see the problematic nature of the
prayers of the New Mass. We simply need to do a quick
compare and contrast. Whereas explicit references
to Catholic dogma saturate the collects, secrets, and
antiphons of the Old Mass, the same cannot be said of
the prayers in the New Mass. When it comes to the
content of the prayers, we do not need inside
information to understand the problem. In fact, one does
not even need to be Catholic to see the
differences in the prayers. One simply has to know what
Catholics teach regarding the Real Presence, the merits
of the saints, propitiation, and the like. Thus, to
focus on the worrying prayers of the New Mass is not to
make an appeal to a properly formed vision, nor is it
even to appeal to specifically Catholic
sensibilities. It’s simply to appeal to facts
about Catholic belief. Any Methodist could tell you, if
(you found one and) had him quickly compare the prayers
of any given Mass for any given day, that one Mass had
more Catholic-rich content than the other.
For this reason, focusing on content is the safest
strategy a traditionalist can take. There is no risk of
offending anyone when we simply focus on the fact that
these prayers do, and these prayers do not, reference
particular Catholic dogmas. It is to simply focus on
facts. Facts, as philosophers point out, do not offend.
Only values do. Moreover, to point out faulty content is
to focus on aspects of the New Mass that do not run the
risk of attacking faulty character. To focus on content
is not to criticize any one parishioner’s taste, and
more importantly, it is not to criticize any one priest.
After all, not only are priests overworked and
underpaid, but they can’t help what they are given to
work with. The prayers are what they are. It is not the
fault of any priest or any parishioner, nor is it a mark
of anyone’s poor taste, that the content of the New Mass
is what it is. Most importantly, to focus on content is
not to present yourself as superior in any way.
In my case in particular, this is quite important, as
such a self-presentation would be impossible.
I’ll probably never get my colleague to appreciate the
joys of a good glass of wine by demanding, again and
again, that he try it. I similarly have had no success
convincing him of the joys of baseball. But I should be
able to convince him of the superiority of the Old Mass,
simply by appealing to his knowledge of Catholicism, and
then showing him the differences in the content of the
prayers of the two Masses. Who knows: perhaps when he
sees the factual differences, he’ll start attending the
Old Mass, and this will start a process that will
properly habituate him, and rightly form his sense of
taste. Before you know it, he’ll be joining me for a
pint in the pub for the night’s game. |