The Debate Thus Far:
Francesco Arzillo’s essay
On Continuity
David Werling’s
Remnant Response
Fr. Giovanni Cavalcoli’s
Defense of Francesco Arzillo
I would like to thank Fr. Giovanni Cavalcoli for the
clarifications he provided concerning Francesco
Arzillo’s arguments. I would also like to thank Fr.
Cavalcoli for taking the time to seriously consider the
traditionalist critique. This is an important
development that would have seemed incredible just a few
years ago. When I was a seminarian back in the late
eighties few would have thought the traditionalist
critique should be taken seriously by respected
theologians, the lay faithful and members of the modern
Magisterium. Yet, here we are today seriously discussing
what would have been considered back then as nothing
short of radical traditionalism. So, whether or not one
agrees with the new hermeneutic of continuity proposed
by the Holy Father, we can thank him, sincerely, for
initiating renewed respect and interest in the
traditionalist critique of the Second Vatican Council
and the crisis in the modern Church.
There remain, however, certain points of contention
concerning Fr. Cavalcoli’s position that require further
clarification and debate. This is particularly the case
in regard to the dichotomy presented between “analogy”
and “univocality”, and the consequences of a lack of the
univocal in the pronouncements of the modern Magisterium,
and specifically in the documents of the Second Vatican
Council.
As I understand the clarification, the heart of
Arzillo’s and Cavalcoli’s argument is their claim that
the traditionalist treats all doctrine as a kind of
Catholic version of the Cartesian “Cogito ergo sum”,
treating of doctrine as the clear and distinct ideas,
which are unchangeable, from which all theological
inquiry proceeds by rigid logical abstraction, with
mathematical precision, to necessary, inescapable and
univocal conclusions. While Arzillo makes an allowance
for dogma to be definitive and unchangeable, other
teachings of the Ordinary Magisterium need be treated
analogously rather than univocally. The traditionalist
position is flawed because it insists on treating
non-definitive teachings of the Magisterium as though
they should be univocal.
Let’s unpack this criticism of the critics. First, the
explanation suggests that “analogy” is at odds with
“univocality”, as though the two were mutually
exclusive. Fr. Cavalcoli does not define “univocality”,
but I’m assuming that he is referring to statements or
propositions that can be said to be univocal. A univocal
statement or proposition is, simply, a proposition or
statement that is unambiguous and unmistakable. Its
meaning is clearly evident. Analogy is a similarity
between two like things from which conclusions can be
drawn from a comparison.
Cavalcoli gives the impression that René Descartes
embraced univocal propositions, while Aristotle avoided
them in favor of the analogous. This is a false
impression. While it is true that Descartes’ “Cogito
ergo sum” is an univocal proposition, it is just as
true that Aristotle’s proposition, “just action is
possible between people who share in things
intrinsically good, and who can have an excess and a
deficiency of them”, is just as univocal as given in
book five, chapter nine, of the Nicomachean Ethics.
Certainly I don’t have to remind Fr. Cavalcoli that St.
Thomas Aquinas’s statement, “et hoc dicimus Deum”,
is as univocal a statement as one can find.
An Aristotelian approach does not avoid the univocal, as
is evident from just a cursory reading of either
Aristotle’s Physics or his Nicomachean Ethics.
Likewise, St. Thomas Aquinas’ Summa Theologica is
rather stacked full of univocal propositions, statements
and conclusions. If univocal propositions are
propositions that are unambiguous, clear and precise,
then the Aristotelian certainly doesn’t shy away from
them, nor does he avoid making necessary distinctions
that are clear and precise. On the contrary, the whole
Aristotelian corpus is an attempt to achieve, with
precision and clarity, univocal conclusions about
reality. If St. Thomas did not write his Summa to
elucidate, to make clear and unambiguous, the truths of
the Catholic religion, then what did he write it for?
Furthermore, analogy can lead to univocal conclusions.
An obvious example that springs to mind is St. Thomas
Aquinas’ fourth proof for the existence of God, which
demonstrates by analogy that “more and less” are
predicated to different things. He concludes,
univocally, “that there must also be something which is
to all beings the cause of their being, goodness, and
every other perfection; and this we call God” (ST I, Q2,
Art 3). Thus, it is clearly evident (pun intended) that
analogy and univocal propositions are not mutually
exclusive.
The difference between the Aristotelian approach and the
Cartesian approach to philosophical inquiry is not
distinguished by an “over dependence” on the univocal
proposition, in either the Cartesian or the Aristotelian
methodology. The univocal proposition has a useful
place, even an exalted place, in both. Rather, the
difference between the two methods of inquiry is that
while the Aristotelian method strives to achieve
univocal propositions that correspond to reality by the
exercise of reasoned inquiry, the Cartesian method
attempts to use the univocal proposition, a clear and
distinct idea, the veracity of which is accepted solely
on the basis of not being subject to speculation, as the
necessary starting point of all inquiry.
However, we are here at the level of inquiry, and the
Church’s Magisterium, while certainly utilizing both
philosophical and theological inquiry, does not endeavor
primarily in either one. The Church’s Magisterium
teaches, it elucidates, it makes clear; in short, its
business is the making of univocal statements.
Obviously, the Magisterium can utilize analogy or any
other methodology to arrive at the univocal statements,
but it does not change the fact that the Church’s
Magisterium isn’t some sort of collective theologian
delving into matters of speculative theology.
Fr. Cavalcoli suggests that the traditionalist, who
eschews analogical thought because of an over dependence
on the univocality, is unable to understand how Catholic
doctrine has developed, progressed, explicated and
clarified itself. Fr. Cavalcoli mentions Blessed John
Henry Newman, but fails to explain the essential points
of Newman’s theory of the development of doctrine.
Allow me to highlight two of the essential points of
Newman’s argument for the development of doctrine.
Newman held that the human mind is such that an idea,
which is necessarily attendant to both the heart and
mind, requires time and polity to accommodate full
comprehension. Before he was elected pontiff, Pope
Benedict XVI once summed this up by stating, “the
individual knows little, but together we know all that
is necessary” (from the short treatise, To Look on
Christ). Joseph Cardinal Ratzinger was drawing upon
this notion of polity and time. The nobler the idea, the
more time and polity are naturally required.
The deposit of Christian faith is the most noble, most
perfect “idea” presented to the human mind and heart,
and thus requires the most time and polity for the human
mind to fully comprehend given aspects of it. However,
the deposit of faith remains, in and of itself,
unchanged. What changes is man’s mental relationship to
it. Man comes to know it more clearly. Blessed John
Henry Newman uses the term “full elucidation” to explain
the process of the development of doctrine
(Introduction, n. 21*). Thus, we can conclude that
authentic development moves in a definite direction,
from less-clear to more-clear to fully-clear, or, dare
we say, toward the univocal!
Secondly, this “full elucidation” is dependent not just
on polity, but also upon a “warrant”. “Certainly a
warrant is necessary; and just such a warrant is the
authority of the Church” (chapter 4, n. 10). Newman
wrote:
Reasons shall be given in this Section for concluding
that, in proportion to the probability of true
developments of doctrine and practice in the Divine
Scheme, so is the probability also of the appointment in
that scheme of an external authority to decide upon
them, thereby separating them from the mass of mere
human speculation, extravagance, corruption, and error,
in and out of which they grow. This is the doctrine of
the infallibility of the Church; for by infallibility I
suppose is meant the power of deciding whether this,
that, and a third, and any number of theological or
ethical statements are true. (Chapter 2, n. 4)
In Newman’s schema, it is not the place of the Church’s
Magisterium to indulge in speculation, but rather to
render judgment, to separate speculation, corruption and
error from what authentically belongs to the deposit of
faith. The Magisterium is the warrant, the guarantee, if
you will, that the development of doctrine moves from
the less-clear, to the more-clear, to the fully-clear.
As St. John Vianney stated in one of his sermons for the
Fourth Sunday after Easter, “in the ever-clearer
definition of the truth consists the progress of
Christianity.”
If this is the role of the Magisterium in the
development of doctrine, how then do we account for the
Magisterium proposing for belief pronouncements that are
unclear, imprecise and ambiguous? If we compare, or use
analogical thinking, to evaluate the admitted
imprecision and ambiguity of the Second Vatican Council
with the development of doctrine as presented by Blessed
John Henry Newman, we are presented with a clear
departure from what has always been understood as
authentic development of doctrine. Indeed, the ambiguity
and imprecision of the documents of Vatican II present
an obvious dissimilarity, and this dissimilarity neither
Arzillo nor Cavalcoli have explained adequately. The
traditionalist critique cannot be dismissed until this
dissimilarity is explained.
Fr. Cavalcoli seems concerned that the traditionalist
critique states or implies that the Second Vatican
Council has taught “something that is false or contrary
to what the Church taught before.” This isn’t the case.
Traditionalists aren’t accusing an Ecumenical Council of
teaching error, but, rather, teaching in a manner that
is unclear and, as a consequence, creates the appearance
of contrariety.
This position does not negate or bemoan the possibility
of disciplinary change in response to historical
circumstances. To use the example provided by Fr.
Cavalcoli, the medieval practice of ocular confession to
only one’s pastor is no longer the discipline of the
Church. However, both then and now, competent authority
has conveyed the discipline in such a way that those
living then knew they could only confess their sins to
their pastor, and those living now know clearly that
they can confess their sins to any priest in good
standing. There is no confusion on the matter not
because of a process of analogical interpretation that
juxtaposes the medieval practice with today’s practice,
but because the Magisterium has clearly taught that this
discipline has changed. This, clear teaching from the
Magisterium indicating that former discipline has
changed, is exactly what is lacking in the documents of
the Second Vatican Council.
This lack of clarity is present, not just in matters of
discipline, but also in matters pertaining to doctrine.
Fr. Cavalcoli states as much when he admits the texts of
the Council are, indeed, obscure. This obscurity is
coupled by a manner of presentation that gives the
impression that what has been already defined, even
dogmatically, is now open to further speculation. If
this were not the case, then there would not have been
the emergence of a “hermeneutic of rupture” in the first
place.
It was gracious of Fr. Cavalcoli to admit that the
imprecise and unclear language of the documents lends
itself to contrary interpretations, “even of the
modernistic kind”. However, what we would like to see
from the Hermeneutic of Continuity Crowd is a serious
consideration of the fact that the very documents of the
Council themselves, because they contain obscure and
imprecise language, are an unwelcome anomaly in the
history of the Church’s Magisterium.
Of course, the faithful can take Fr. Cavalcoli’s advice.
The faithful can consult the Catechism of the Catholic
Church, but it also contains problematic passages. The
faithful can wait for the Magisterium to make doctrinal
condemnations, which come about once every twenty years
or so. In the case of Bishop William Morris it took the
Vatican over a decade to finally clarify a number of
troublesome doctrinal and disciplinary aberrations on
the part of the Australian bishop. The faithful can wait
for any number of clarifications from the Vatican
regarding the documents; for example, it only took forty
years to see a clarification of “subsistit in”.
At the rate modernist and liberal positions are
condemned and troublesome aspects of the documents are
clarified, we should have all the obscurities contained
in the Vatican II documents cleared up in… say… three
centuries?
I don’t mean to be facetious. These options aren’t
exactly an acceptable answer to the imposition that has
been placed on the faithful, here and now living out
their vocations in the trenches of the spiritual combat.
The lack of clarity has caused a serious upheaval in the
Church, a crisis that has reached an intolerable
crescendo. This is a serious matter, and as the crisis
in the Church plays out before us, it is evident that
the salvation of souls hangs in the balance. Granted,
there is a perceptible shift in the Church in recent
years. This debate is evidence enough of that. However,
the situation is still rather urgent, and amends should
not be delayed.
But from whence are these amends to be forthcoming when
the Magisterium is only just now beginning to emerge
from the “spirit of Vatican II”? Fr. Cavalcoli mentions
his present endeavor with Fr. Enrico Finotti and Fr.
Piero Cantoni to pen a book in which “we propose to
demonstrate the doctrinal continuity between the Council
and the previous magisterium through careful comparison
of the official texts of the Church.” However, allow me
to repeat what Roberto de Mattei has already made clear:
the faithful do not submit to the opinions and positions
of theologians, no matter how erudite and orthodox they
may be; rather, the faithful are to submit to the
Magisterium of the Church. While I’m sure we will
greatly appreciate the work of Fathers Cavalcoli,
Finotti and Cantoni, this book simply will not
substitute for the clear, and yes, univocal! teaching
that the Magisterium of the Church is supposed to
provide.
Until that time Catholics ought to have the option to
continue to believe and practice the Catholicism that
Catholics in centuries past believed and practiced to
their credit and salvation. After all, what was
considered sacred and good before cannot all of a sudden
be considered evil or wrong now. This is certainly not
an ideal that should content us, especially traditional
Catholics. This is, perhaps, a sad, but necessary
fallback position imposed on the sincere faithful who
see no other choice due to the negligence of those who
should have taught, and ought to be teaching now, the
truths of the faith clearly and without fear. To have to
live by a hermeneutic is a perilous imposition. To live
as a traditional Catholic? To that there is no
imposition at all.
(22
May 2011, Fourth Sunday After Easter)
_________________
*Newman, John Henry. An Essay on the Development of
Christian Doctrine. Longmans, Green, and Co. London.
1909.
|