A Real Catholic
Monarchy
John C. Médaille
REMNANT COLUMNIST, Texas
Real Catholics
A
short while ago, a Mr. Michael Voris, who calls himself “The
Real Catholic,” called for America to change its system of
government from a democracy to a “benevolent” Catholic
dictatorship, a system Mr. Voris called a “Catholic
Monarchy.” In Mr. Voris's ideal system, voting, to the
extent it would be allowed at all, would be confined to
Catholics. Now, I am always a little uncomfortable with
people who call themselves the “real” anything; I cannot get
over the feeling that were I to venture a contrary opinion,
I would be considered less “real,” or in this case perhaps
outright heretical. Nevertheless, at the risk of losing my
reality, I must beg to disagree with His Realness. I think a
real Catholic might have consulted some really Catholic
sources on the question, sources such as St. Thomas Aquinas.
Real Regalism
More
of what the good saint says in a moment, but first let me
point out that what the Real Catholic is advocating is not a
true monarchy at all, but a system which Dr. John Rao has
called “Regalism.” Regalism was a development of the late
Middle Ages and early modern period that sought to
centralize all power in the hands of the king. All social
and economic institutions, even—or especially—the Church,
were brought under royal control. This was the beginning of
the modern “nation-state,” in which all loyalties, and all
power, were transferred to the state in the person of the
king; from there it was but a short step to replace the
all-powerful king with an oligarchy or a democracy, or more
usually, an oligarchy disguised as a democracy.
Regalism was, we might say, “non-denominational”; it was
practiced by both Catholic and Protestant monarchs. Long
before the Reformation, the state was expanding its power at
the expense of the Church. The taxing of the clergy, the
consolidation of ecclesial courts into civil ones, intrusion
into the educational system, the replacement of the Church’s
charities with the welfare state, and royal control of
clerical appointments were some of the signs of the
expanding power of the state. The Reformation merely
continued this process, since so many of the “reformers”
were more than willing to replace the pope with the prince
to enforce a confessional conformity. The Reformation
depended on lay power, and gave a justification for that
power, but the way had been prepared by Catholic monarchs.
And while the Catholic kings never succeeded in having
themselves declared head of the Church in their realms, they
came very close. For example, Pope Julius III could write to
the French King Henry II, “You are more than pope in your
kingdoms,” and when Richelieu was appointed Cardinal, he
sent his letter of thanks not to the pope, but to the king,
the real religious power in France.
Nowhere was this royal control more damaging to the Church's
mission than in the case of the missions. The king's writ
extended to distant lands, and the missions became another
instrument of state power in which nationalism dominated
over salvation. Missionary activity was subordinated to
commercial and political objectives, thereby making the work
of the Church seem like a mere instrument of what would
later be called “colonialism.” The national control of the
missions created tremendous jurisdictional problems, so that
the new believers didn't know which authority to believe, as
bishops from the home country vied with vicars from the
Vatican. And the nationalist missions impeded the
development of native clergy, since this could form a source
of opposition to royal control. Tremendous opportunities
were lost in Japan and China, losing not only billions of
souls for Christ, but changing the course of history;
imagine how different things would be today if these
oriental powers had become Catholic.
This
regalism was a vast departure from the norm of medieval
monarchies. Rather than a plenary authority, subjugating all
to the royal will, medieval kings tended to have a limited
authority as heads of a rich network of social institutions,
each with their own domain, authority, and dignity. There
was of course the Church, but also the guilds, the towns,
barons great and small, universities, and associations of
all sorts. The king's writ might run as law, but there was
very little he could actually write in his writ, given the
plurality of powers that surrounded him. People were
conscious of their rights and privileges, and willing to
fight for them, as Richard II of England discovered when he
tried to impose a poll tax (essentially, an income tax) on
the people, and found that within a few weeks a vast peasant
army swept through the kingdom to capture both London and
the king. Treachery got Richard out of his difficulties, but
he was made very aware of the limitations to his power. In
fact, a modern bureaucrat, in the normal course of his day,
exercises more power than a medieval king; the bureaucrat
can, with a stroke of a pen, take away your business or your
children, thereby making tyranny a sort of daily routine;
the bureaucrat's writ does indeed run as law, as long as the
proper forms are filled out.
I
dwell on the problems of regalism because it is this version
of “monarchy” which is most familiar to the general public.
Whatever the faults of the American Founders, this was the
kind of monarchy that justified the revolution. The same
principle that was applied in the last article to democracy
also applies to monarchy. That is, a thing without proper
limits becomes its own opposite, and benevolence quickly
becomes a tyranny which threatens both civil and religious
order. But Catholics can look to a wider tradition to
meditate on these matters; we need not confine our
meditations on monarchy to King George III, or even to King
Louis XVI, Catholic as he may have been.
Real Monarchy
Preeminent among our sources is St. Thomas Aquinas. In his
letter to the King of Cypress, he identified monarchy as
both the best and worst form of government; best when the
king acted for the common good, and worst when he did not.
But of course, kings and queens are but men and women in
regal robes, and greed rages in their hearts no less than in
the hearts of the commons, and a king no less than a
commoner is likely to be ruled by unruly passions. So just
as a democracy needs a monarchial limit, the monarchy needs
aristocratic and democratic limits. As to how this is to be
accomplished, St. Thomas says:
Accordingly, the best form of government is in a state or
kingdom, wherein one is given the power to preside over all;
while under him are others having governing powers: and yet
a government of this kind is shared by all, both because all
are eligible to govern, and because the rules are chosen by
all. For this is the best form of polity, being partly
kingdom, since there is one at the head of all; partly
aristocracy, in so far as a number of persons are set to
authority; partly democracy, i.e., government by the people,
in so far as the rulers can be chosen from the people and
the people have the right to choose their leaders. (ST I-11,
105.1)
We can
ask, “If the people have the right to choose their leaders,
what is the purpose of the monarchy?” St Thomas defines this
as giving a unity to the people in order to direct all to
the common good, which is a “unity of peace” and a concern
for justice. “Peace” in this context means much more than
just the absence of war. Rather, it is an internal harmony
in the kingdom that directs all levels to justice, for
“Everything is uncertain when there is a departure from
justice” (De Regno, 26). Politics tends to be divisive by
its very nature; even when people attempt to act for the
common good, they also tend to interpret that good according
to their own needs and desires. Some principle in government
needs to have the possibility of interpreting the common
good from the standpoint of the whole society, a good which
encompasses all, from the lowest to the highest.
However, the term “common good,” standing by itself, tends
to be rather vague and needs some development before it can
be useful. The Catholic Church has developed two further
principles in guiding rulers to the common good. These
principles are not mere abstractions, not the result of
isolated philosophers and theologians dictating what they
think is good for society. Rather, they are the result of
the Church's reflection on its 2,000 years of experience
with governments of all sorts. These principles are
subsidiarity and solidarity.
Subsidiarity is a principle which stands the political
hierarchy on its head; it states that the higher levels of
government exist only to serve the lowest. A higher level of
authority can be justified only by the aid (subsidium)
it gives to the lower level, and especially to the lowest
unit of society, the family. The royal family, the first
family of the kingdom, is in a sense the last family, and
the king, who is the greatest of all, must become the
servant of all, in the same way that the pope is the
servus servorum dei, “the servant of the servants of
God.”
Solidarity
is the principle which requires that every action of
government must be evaluated on the basis of how it affects
the poorest citizens, and if it harms this group, it is
likely not a just action to begin with. Its signature is a
“preferential option for the poor,” and it forms a kind of
acid test for the common good.
Note
that Thomas does not give specific duties or authorities for
each element of government. And that is proper, because the
actual distribution of authority is not something derived
from the natural law. Rather, it is a prudential judgment
that changes from culture to culture, and with time and
circumstance. For the character of peoples and nations vary,
and the needs of the times change with the times; therefore
their particular institutions must evolve from their own
experiences and needs. Nevertheless, there are some general
principles that we might advance, though they might be
modified to fit any particular political tradition.
Concerning the king, he needs to have real authority, an
authority that extends to the executive, legislative, and
judicial functions. Of course, he should not be the only
authority in these areas, nor even necessarily the ordinary
authority; but he should, in some sense, be the ultimate
authority. The king's government also needs to have its own
revenue stream, one fixed in the constitution and
independent of any legislative body. A king who has to beg
his bread from the legislature is no king, and whoever holds
the power of the purse will soon hold all other powers. The
legislature may by its own will supplement the
constitutional revenues, perhaps to pay for a war or some
other extraordinary expense, and they may control the funds
they levy. But for the budgeting of the constitutional
revenue, the king should be primary, or even the sole,
authority. Other authorities may comment, they may even
censure a king, such as when a king neglects the defense of
the realm to build himself palaces. But in the practical
world, control of the budget is control of everything else.
The king should also hold an absolute veto over both the
legislature and the judicial functions. And finally, there
needs to be a difficult but peaceful means of removing a
king; without this, kings themselves become the cause of
revolutions.
The
more difficult question actually concerns the aristocracy.
Both Aristotle and Aquinas thought of aristocracy in terms
of virtue and accomplishment rather than in terms of birth
and wealth. The latter they considered to be a mere
oligarchy. However, men often confuse wealth with worth, and
this is especially true of the men with an excess of wealth
and an absence of worth. In my opinion, even in cases where
there is a requirement of wealth or birth, there should
still be a selection process to choose the best of the
wealthy or well-born. But whatever the process, the function
of the aristocracy is virtue. I interpret this to mean that
they should be a source of impartial commentary and judgment
on political affairs. In the next installment, I will deal
in greater detail with some solutions to the aristocratic
problem.
Finally, there is the democratic problem. Democracy works
best at the local level, and a national democracy is almost
a contradiction in itself, since the staggering costs of
national campaigns enforce an oligarchic control. Nor can
this problem be solved by some sort of campaign finance
reform or even public funding of elections, unless we are
willing to forbid all political speech, save that funded by
the public purse. But that would be a form of tyranny in
itself. The best way to reduce the cost of elections is to
make the districts small, which will keep the cost of
campaigning cheap, and hence less susceptible to oligarchic
control. Small districts imply large legislatures, and this
has the advantage of making them slow and unwieldy, able to
agree on laws only when they are most necessary. But if one
wants a small and more agile legislature, then perhaps it
would be wise to chose it by indirect elections, with
electors chosen at the neighborhood level, who then meet in
an assembly to choose the actual legislators. In any case,
deliberative forms of democracy, such as the caucus or the
town meeting, should be favored over electoral forms, such
as secret ballot. But whatever the size and composition of
the legislature, it should have clearly defined and limited
powers.
However, all of these reflections, whether right or wrong,
good or bad, remain sterile if there is no way to realize
them in the existing political order. As interesting as they
might be, such speculations are of great value only if they
can be led to actions which are effective in the given
political order. Even a remnant wants to be effective, to
have some actual impact in the world. Political systems
arise not solely from mere theorizing, but from actual
experience. The task is to examine the current situation,
and see what can be done, in this time of crisis, to make
the political system more monarchial, which is to say more
truly democratic. That will be the burden of my next essay. |