(www.RemnantNewspaper.com)
The announcement that one is a monarchist is greeted
with the same regard as the announcement that one has
joined the Flat-Earth Society, or espouses geo-centrism,
or has expressed a belief in a world only 6,000 years
old.
Politically, monarchism has a prestige just a tiny bit
better than fascism, but not nearly as respectable as
being Amish. Therefore, it behooves me to cut directly
to the chase, and state very clearly why I am a
monarchist: I am a monarchist because I am a democrat.
That is, I believe that the will of the people, their
traditions and customs, their concern for their
families, their communities, and for the future should
determine the shape of any political order. And monarchy
is the highest form of this democracy.
Now, the first response to that is likely to be, “That
is what our democracy does, and what a tyranny doesn’t
do; democracy enthrones the will of the people, while
monarchy enthrones the will of the tyrant.” But it is
clear to me, especially in this late date of our
democracy, that it enthrones the will of determined and
well-financed minorities, that it dissolves the customs
and traditions of the people, and that it has no concern
for the future. And a king may indeed be a tyrant, but
such is the exception rather than the rule.
Tyranny is a degeneration of proper monarchy and
generally happens only in degenerate times, and even
then, the king has to be speaking for some other and
greater force, such as a strong army or a commercial
oligarchy. A king, no less than a president, must
consider the forces and interests in his kingdom. But a
king is free to judge the justice of the arguments; a
president is free only to count the votes. And while the
president might attempt to engage in persuasion, in the
end he himself can only be persuaded by power, that is,
by whoever controls the votes, which is very likely to
be the one who controls the money. A king may also be
persuaded by power and money, but he is always free to
be persuaded by justice. And even when a king is a
tyrant, he is an identifiable tyrant; much worse is when
a people live in a tyranny they may not name, a system
where the forms of democracy serve as cover for the
reality of tyranny. And that, I believe, is our
situation today.
This thesis requires some extended explication, and I
will explore it in three parts. First, a critique of
electoral democracy as it actually exists; second, an
explication of a monarchist polity; and finally, an
examination of American institutions which could evolve,
in times of trouble, into more monarchical (and
therefore more democratic) forms.
The Dogma of Democracy
Modern democracy has come to mean, in preference to all
other possible forms, electoral democracy, where
the officers of the state are chosen in periodic
plebiscites determined by secret ballot. This has long
since been the dominant form, and has become, in common
usage, the only meaning of democracy. In the last 100
years we have fought numerous wars to make the world
“safe” for this form; it is as if we believed that the
right level of shock and awe would turn the citizens of
Baghdad into good Republicans and Democrats, or convert
Afghanistan into a suburb of Seattle.
Since this democracy is something we are willing to both
kill and die for, it assumes the status of a religion,
albeit a secular one. Like all religions, electoral
democracy has its central sacrament, its central
liturgy, and its central dogma; its sacrament is the
secret ballot, its liturgy is the election campaign, and
its dogma is that the election will represent the will
of the people.
But is this dogma true in any sense? Is the “will of the
people” really captured by 51% of the voters? Clearly,
not everyone votes, so the will of the voters may not at
all be the will of the people. One might respond that it
is the will of the people who cared enough to vote.
However, that ignores the fact that there are people
(like myself) who care enough not to vote; people
who find no party acceptable, or worse, find that both
parties are really the same party with cosmetic
differences for the entertainment and manipulation of
the public.
I
suspect that if there were a real choice on the ballot,
such as a box marked “none of the above,” turnout would
be higher, and this last choice the consistent winner.
But in any case, it is not true that the will of a bare
majority of the voters can easily be equated with the
“will of the people.”
Further, we can ask if a bare majority is actually a
sufficient margin for any really important decision, one
that commits everyone to endorse serious and
abiding actions. For example, should 51% be allowed to
drag the rest into war? Or into the continuing war
against children that is abortion? Certainly, there are
issues that can rightly be decided by bare majorities,
but the important issues cannot fall in that category.
There is yet another problem with the dogma of
representation, because there are clearly two groups
which elections cannot canvass: the dead, and the yet
unborn, the past and the future. In an electoral
democracy, the interests of the living predominate. Now,
as to the first group, some say that we should not be
bound by the dead past, and that our first freedom is
freedom from our parents. There is, of course, a grain
of truth in this; death is there for a reason.
Nevertheless, life is bigger than the present moment,
and no generation, no matter how scientific, can grasp
the totality of life, can completely discern the correct
way of living in the world.
The world as it is at any given moment is the result of
decisions and actions that make up its past. The
traditions we receive are the sum total of the distilled
wisdom of the past about how to live in the world and
with each other. It is, of course, an incomplete
knowledge, and our task is to add to it, and to pass it
on. Tradition therefore comes from the past but is
oriented to the future. But democracies tend to erode
traditions by pandering to current desires. G. K.
Chesterton has labeled tradition “the democracy of the
dead,” and a real democracy will accommodate these
absent constituents.
In
abandoning the past, democracy also abandons the future.
We pile the children with debts they cannot pay, wars
they cannot win, obligations they cannot meet; we allow
the infrastructure to deteriorate and so weaken even
their ability to earn a living. We vote ourselves large
pensions at an early age, confident that we can live on
the taxes paid by the children, even as we restrict the
number of children we have, placing an even bigger
burden on the ones that remain.
But in abandoning both the past and the future,
democracy abandons even the ability to represent the
present, because without the guidance of the past and
the concern for the future, even the present moment
loses its reality. The present moment is always
ephemeral, because as soon as one grasps it, it is
already history. Without tradition and an orientation to
the future, the present moment becomes a kind of
cultural Alzheimer’s, with no memory and no direction.
The Liturgy of Democracy
And if the dogma is wrong, the liturgy—the election
campaign—is troubling. In truth, elections are
markets with very high entry costs. To run for a
party’s presidential nomination, a candidate might need
$50 million in his pocket just to be credible. This will
not come near his or her total expenses; it is just the
down payment. It doesn’t buy the election, it just buys
credibility, and without such credibility (i.e., money)
one will not be covered by the press. The total expenses
will be a multiple of that down payment.
Indeed, in the 2008 elections, campaign costs were a
staggering $5.3 billion, and that was just for
the national races. There are very limited sources for
that kind of money, and the political process must,
perforce, be dominated by those sources. The
corporations and organizations that fund elections do so
as an investment, one on which they expect a superior
rate of return. And they get it, in the form of
subsidies, favorable laws and regulations, access to
high officials, and tax breaks. It may be the best
investment most big businesses make. But it leads
directly to oligarchy, the opposite of democracy, a
Republic of the PACs rather than a polity of the people.
And why is so much money needed? Because the political
arts in a democracy are not the arts of deliberation and
persuasion, which are relatively inexpensive, but are
the arts of manipulation and propaganda, which are
extremely costly. The appeal is almost never to the
intelligence, but to raw passion and emotion. The path
to power in a democracy, the surest way to ensure the
loyalty of one’s followers, is to exaggerate small
differences into great “issues.” Candidates must find a
way to distinguish themselves from each other, even (or
especially) if they are in fundamental agreement. And
the more irrational an issue is, the better it is for
the purposes of manipulation. Real issues can be the
subject of real arguments, and voters might be persuaded
by such arguments, which would erode the fanatical
devotion that politicians require. Thus, it is better to
debate the issue of whether Obama is a Muslim rather
than whether he grasps the mechanics of a financial
crisis; the former is the subject of a passionate and
fact-free debate, but the latter requires knowledge and
intelligence.
The supreme act of democratic manipulation is the
creation of the demonic “other.” Those of a different
party are portrayed not as people who in all sincerity
start with different assumptions and reach different
conclusions, but as deliberate and demonic destroyers of
the social and political order. Reason is replaced by
fear, and if the “other side” is always feared, then
one’s own performance doesn’t really matter; no matter
how inept one party proves itself, it can always make
the appeal that the other party is demonic. To be sure,
there are assumptions and opinions which do tear down
society, but there are few, if any, who hold their
opinions for the purpose of destroying the social order;
rather they have a different, if often erroneous, vision
of that order.
This demonizing tendency is most clearly seen when
democracy is imposed on nations that have diverse
ethnic, cultural, and religious elements. While there is
always a certain tension in such societies,
nevertheless, under the rule of kings, empires, or even
dictatorships, they find a way of living together in
relative peace. But with the coming of electoral
democracy, each group and tribe demonizes the other, and
the result is civil war, ethnic cleansing, and genocide.
Indeed, ethnic cleansing has become the highest act of
democratic order. I cannot recall a single exception to
this rule. We have truly made the world safe for
democracy; unfortunately, we have made democracy unsafe
for the world.
The Sacrament of Democracy
With minor exceptions, democracy takes place in the
“sacred” space of the voting booth, which resembles
nothing so much as the Catholic confessional. And
indeed, this is the place where the voter, alone and
isolated, confesses his true religion. It is, perhaps,
the highest expression of the individualist philosophy
of modern man. But one might ask if such individualism
is compatible with democracy itself, or indeed, any
reasonable form of community. In modernist
utilitarianism, there is no common good, no objective
goods at all. “Good” means only “good for me” and voting
merely an expression of self-interest. So therefore,
things like, say, abortion are not “good” or “bad,” but
only “good for me,” and elections merely about summing
the private goods.
But the secret ballot is not the only form of voting.
There are deliberative forms: the caucus, the town
meeting, the group assembly, more suitable to reaching a
common good. Voting in these systems is public, and a
space is allowed for deliberation and public persuasion.
And in such forums, the argument “this is good for me”
is not persuasive; only arguments in the form of “this
is good for us” or simply “this is good” can
persuade.
It is true that any group can be as irrational, or more
so, than isolated individuals. Nevertheless, in a group
there is always the possibility that persons of reason
and temperance will be able to persuade their fellow
citizens to a reasonable course of action, and overcome
the natural tendency of democracy to passion and
irrationality.
If the voting booth is like the confessional, the
caucus is more like communion.
Is Democracy Democratic?
When we look at our political order, we may truly ask if
this is what we really wanted, if the true will of the
people is expressed in our institutions. Oddly enough,
both Republicans and Democrats, liberals and
conservatives, express grave doubts that this is so.
Indeed, this may be the only point of agreement between
the two sides; they both conclude that something has
gone terribly wrong.
Let me suggest that the answer lies in modern
absolutism. A thing is known by its proper limits, and a
thing without limits becomes its own opposite. Thus
democracy, sacralized and absolutized, becomes its own
opposite, a thinly disguised oligarchy of power which
uses all the arts of propaganda to convince the public
that their votes matter. There is precedent for this.
The Western Roman Empire maintained the Republican form
and offices. Consul, quaestor, aedile, and tribune
remained and there were hotly contested and highly
expensive campaigns for these offices. The army still
marched under the banner not of the emperor, but of the
SPQR, “The Senate and People of Rome.” But of course it
was all a sham; real power lay with the emperor and with
the army and the merchant/landowning classes whose
interests he largely represented, while buying off the
plebs with the world’s largest welfare state. But at
least the Romans could see their emperor, could know his
name, could love him or hate him. We are not permitted
to see our real rulers, and never permitted to name
them. The democratic sham covers the oligarchic reality.
All that being said, one may still ask, “Would things
have been better had we stayed with King George? After
all, it doesn’t seem to have helped the British, who
resemble no one so much as the Americans.” This
statement, while sure to offend my English friends,
nevertheless contains a kernel of truth, and a question
that must be answered. For in truth the notion of
monarchy had, by that time, undergone its own period of
absolutism to become its own opposite as well, and the
German kings of England were there by the sufferance of
oligarchic powers.
To
get a true idea of kingship, we will have to go back a
bit, not merely to the middle ages, but even as far back
as Aristotle. And that will be the subject of my next
installment. |